Brede moraal en brede rede | Amsterdam University Press Journals Online
2004
Volume 114 Number 1
  • ISSN: 0002-5275
  • E-ISSN: 2352-1244

Abstract

Abstract

Many of today’s problems revolve around distance and proximity. Progressives argue that a universalist, inclusive ethics requires us to bridge distances in identity, space, and time. Conservatives object that such bridging is psychologically unrealistic: people of flesh and blood can only care about whom/what is close-by. Evolutionary and psychological research seems to corroborate this sobering view. Many researchers confirm that our intuitions (‘System 1’) are groupish and short-sighted, and largely deaf to the appeal of rational universalism (‘System 2’).

But not all agree. We distinguish four ‘evo-progressive’ attempts to reconcile evolution and psychology with a universalist, inclusive ethics. Singer and Pinker (1), Buchanan and Powell (2), and Sunstein (3) contend that a reason-based, inclusive ethics is psychologically feasible, but that such an ethics has to be thin, solely focusing on rights and no-harm. By contrast, Haidt (4) argues that an inclusive ethics should be ‘broad’, also encompassing moral domains like sacrality, loyalty and authority. This implies for him that it cannot be reason-based.

We argue that a broad form of inclusive ethics can and should be reason-based, but that this requires a rethinking of ‘reason’. We show that the evo-progressives’ conviction that a rational ethics is by definition thin, results from their theoreticistic conception of reason. But reason can also have more mimetic-embodied or mythical-narrative forms. These do allow for a broad, rational, inclusive ethics that can motivate real people to include stakeholders that are distant in identity, place, and time.

Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.5117/ANTW2022.1.002.SWIE
2022-04-01
2024-03-28
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

References

  1. Bellah, R. N. (2011) Religion in Human Evolution. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  2. Bentham, J. (1996) The collected works of Jeremy Bentham: An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  3. Buchanan, A. en Powell, R. (2015) The Limits of Evolutionary Explanations of Morality and Their Implications for Moral Progress. Ethics, 126(1), pp. 37-67. doi.org/10.1086/682188
    [Google Scholar]
  4. Buchanan, A. en Powell, R. (2016) Toward a Naturalistic Theory of Moral Progress. Ethics, 126(4), pp. 983-1014. doi.org/10.1086/686003
    [Google Scholar]
  5. Buchanan, A. en Powell, R. (2018) The evolution of moral progress: A biocultural theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  6. Cohen, G. A. (2000) If you’re an egalitarian, how come you’re so rich. The Journal of ethics, 4(1), pp. 1-26.
    [Google Scholar]
  7. Darwin, C. (2008) [1871] The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  8. De Waal, F. (2006) Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  9. Donald, M. (2012) An Evolutionary Approach to Culture, in: The axial age and its consequences. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press, pp. 47-76.
    [Google Scholar]
  10. Engelen, B., Thomas, A., Archer, A. en Van de Ven, N. (2018) Exemplars and nudges: Combining two strategies for moral education. Journal of Moral Education, 47(3), pp. 346-365.
    [Google Scholar]
  11. European Commission, Joint Research Centre (2020) Technology and democracy: understanding the influence of online technologies on political behaviour and decision making. Publications Office. https://data.europa.eu/doi/10.2760/593478
    [Google Scholar]
  12. Fiske, S. T. (2013) Varieties of (de) humanization: Divided by competition and status, in: Objectification and (de) humanization. New York: Springer, pp. 53-71.
    [Google Scholar]
  13. Flanagan, O. (1991) Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  14. Hertwig, R. en Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017) Nudging and boosting: Steering or empowering good decisions. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12(6), pp. 973-986.
    [Google Scholar]
  15. Haidt, J. (2012) The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.
    [Google Scholar]
  16. Haraway, D. J. (2016) Staying with the Trouble. Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Durham: Duke University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  17. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J. en Norenzayan, A. (2010) The weirdest people in the world?Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), pp. 61-83. doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X0999152X
    [Google Scholar]
  18. Hirschman, A. O. (2013) [1977] The passions and the interests. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  19. Jonas, H. (1979) Das Prinzip Verantwortung: Versuch einer Ethik für die technologische Zivilisation. Berlijn: Insel Verlag.
    [Google Scholar]
  20. Keulartz, J. (2021) Boom mensen. Over nut en nadeel van de humanisering van de natuur. Gorredijk: Noordboek Natuur.
    [Google Scholar]
  21. Nagel, T. (1989). The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  22. Kahneman, D. (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Londen: Allen Lane.
    [Google Scholar]
  23. Margalit, A. (2017) On betrayal. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  24. McCaffree, K. (2015) What morality means: An interdisciplinary synthesis for the social sciences. Dordrecht: Springer.
    [Google Scholar]
  25. Mercier, H. en Sperber, D. (2017) The enigma of reason. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  26. Mullainathan, S. en Shafir, E. (2012) Scarcity: Why having too little means so much. MacMillan.
    [Google Scholar]
  27. Pinker, S. (2011) The Better Angels of Our Nature: The Decline of Violence, in: History and Its Causes. Londen: Penguin UK.
    [Google Scholar]
  28. Reesink, M. (2021) Dier en mens. De band tussen ons en andere dieren. Amsterdam: Boom.
    [Google Scholar]
  29. Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M. en Park, L. (1997) The ‘big three’ of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the ‘big three’ explanations of suffering, in: Morality and health. Londen: Taylor & Frances/Routledge, pp. 119-169.
    [Google Scholar]
  30. Stuurman, S. (2010) De uitvinding van de mensheid: Korte wereldgeschiedenis van het denken over gelijkheid en cultuurverschil. Amsterdam: Bert Bakker.
    [Google Scholar]
  31. Sunstein, C. R. (2005) Moral heuristics. Behavioral and brain sciences, 28(4), 531-541.
    [Google Scholar]
  32. Sunstein, C. R. (2016). The ethics of influence: Government in the age of behavioral science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  33. Thaler, R. H. en Sunstein, C. R. (2009). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Londen: Penguin.
    [Google Scholar]
  34. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124-1131. doi.org/10.1126/science.185.4157.1124
    [Google Scholar]
  35. Weber, M. (1978) Economy and Society. Berkeley: University of California Press.
    [Google Scholar]
  36. Woodruff, P. (2014) Reverence: Renewing a forgotten virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    [Google Scholar]
http://instance.metastore.ingenta.com/content/journals/10.5117/ANTW2022.1.002.SWIE
Loading
/content/journals/10.5117/ANTW2022.1.002.SWIE
Loading

Data & Media loading...

This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was a Success
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error